BOOK TWO Chapter 18
The Logic 1812 to 1816
In several instances, Rosenkranz’ chapters on Hegel’s published books are
disappointingly sketchy, though interesting all the same, and this one on the
Science of Logic (1812-16) fits the pattern.
He starts by saying that Nuremberg, with its ditches outside town walls and views of
the country from crowded streets, is a city of contrasting movements aloft and
downwards.
The tempos of life of its Slav and Franconian inhabitants also contrast with each other. In this town be wrote his Science of Logic, published between March 1812 and July 1816 according to the dates on the prefaces. [The relation of the topography of the town to the book Hegel wrote there occured to me spontanteously on my visit there, though I would add that the church towers added to the sense of movement.] Hegel described the social life of the town in a letter to Knebel (14/12/1810). Here:
The tempos of life of its Slav and Franconian inhabitants also contrast with each other. In this town be wrote his Science of Logic, published between March 1812 and July 1816 according to the dates on the prefaces. [The relation of the topography of the town to the book Hegel wrote there occured to me spontanteously on my visit there, though I would add that the church towers added to the sense of movement.] Hegel described the social life of the town in a letter to Knebel (14/12/1810). Here:
"Hegel finished his Logic which erected the towers of the eternal categories in the element of purest abstraction."
The Logic follows the Phenomenology which was an introduction to the system. Leaving aside
the development of consciousness to maturity in the Phenomenology, the Logic is the first part of the system
as such and thus serves to make the Phenomenology itself
comprehensible, for it shows pure knowledge in itself rather than knowledge in
relation and also gives, or rather is, an example of the method recommended in the
Phenomenology.
Logic and metaphysics, Hegel argues, lag behind the other sciences. A
people without metaphysics is as astonishing as one with no constitutional
theory, he remarks. Mind has achieved a new form, but this needs scientific
development. Hegel writes:
“As science, truth is the pure self-consciousness developing itself and it has the form of self[hood]; this in and for itself is the known concept; whilst the concept as such is in-and-for-itself.” (448)
Thus
Hegel rejects the idea of Logic as a realm of logical forms indifferent to the
matter or content of knowledge. We are dealing with objective thought in
Logic, a standpoint which Hegel also terms metaphysics (e.g. in the contemporary Propaedeutic).
Rosenkranz recounts that the equation of Logic with God prior to creation
stupefied the theologians, then tries to explain it by treating it as a
residue. Hegel also stupefied logicians who saw logical forms as subjective.
Also, the positive sciences were sceptical of an apparently a priori
aspect to their subject matter. “It never came into Hegel’s head to deny the
concrete in such a lazy fashion.” (449) Rather, nature is a surpassing/transcendence
(dépassement) of Logic, as Mind is of Nature. One cannot find much in
the Logic starting from concrete sciences. Being is not some particular being,
for example.
Terminology
In his terminology, Hegel either borrows from German as it has developed
since the 14th century, as in Wesen, for example, or forges new terms
after the Greek fashion of Plato and Aristotle, though the Greeks were often
more audacious than he (e.g. to ti en einai, entelecheia [essence, end-state]).
Hence in German we have:
- Fürsichsein
- Ansichsein
- Anundfürsichsein
- Sichselbstgleichheit
These are terms of art in other words, the intended meaning of which is most fully indicated in the Logic, though they are used already in the Phenomenology.
The Content
Hegel compares the theory of syllogism to arithmetic, as forms of calculus.
Living thought on the other hand needs to know that contradictions do not
resolve to zero, that a negative is just as much a positive result. Only a
particular thing is negated. [Osmo the French translator equates chose
and causa in translating Sache rather than
Ding.] A richer concept emerges from the wreckage of such thinking.
Hegel recognises as merits in Kant the identification of the categories as forms of self-consciousness and the exposition of contradiction as a feature of dialectical reason. However, seeing the categories as subjective and contradiction only as negative are faults, he thinks, for reason has means to overcome contradiction and is only a moment of an affirmative unity (453).
Hegel divides ontological and ideological (that is, objective and
subjective) Logic, but with a middle point of essence, where the terms do not
pass into one another, as in quality, quantity and measure, but have meaning
only as contrasts. i.e.
- identity and difference- content and form
- cause and effect
The Doctrine of the Concept
The Doctrine of the Concept is the most original part of the book, thinks Rosenkranz. The
determinations of the Concept are a unity of immediacy and mediation. Thus they
develop, or else each moment is the whole. In other words, the material divides
itself into the particular, which is realised in the individual. This is interesting, but in my view it is unfortunate that the scope of the assertions is not more clearly indicated.
In the doctrine of the Concept, Hegel discusses his relation to Kant and
the relations of Logic and the real. He equates Being with intuition and
sensation, or with space and time; essence with representation and perception,
or inorganic nature; and the Concept with self-consciousness, or organic
nature. But the logical forms are independent of their realisation.
The step at the end of the Logic to nature is “ein freies Entlassen” (a
free releasing). Rosenkranz points out that this Entlassung is on the part of
the Idea. i.e. conceived in unity with the real. He brings in St John’s Gospel,
but says that Hegel is not being gnostic or logo-theistic, as Schelling later
alleged. Neither was St John by the way, or so it is widely thought (e.g. by T F Torrance).
From 1812, Hegel was pursued by criticism of his ideas on the “identity of
being and non-being”. Rosenkranz refers here to a correspondence with Pfaff, a
mathematician, on Hegel’s views of Newton and the differential calculus, which
survives on Pfaff’s side only.
Footnote:
From the discussion on the Hegel-list, it emerged that the Kantian distinction of a priori and a posteriori plays little role in Hegel's Logic. Perhaps, I felt, the following quote sheds light on
Rosenkranz’ interpretation of Hegel's Logic:
“Hegel never disputed the necessity of experience as such, but he well and truly showed how, by its own contradictions, it [thought] pushes onward from itself to universality and to the necessity of determinations.” (from Rosenkranz, op cit: Book 3 chapter 2)
Thanks for sharing these brief notes Private Tutor Gilbert
ReplyDeleteThe notes are amazing Special Needs Tutor Scottsdale
ReplyDeleteThese brief notes are useful Private Tutor Greater Heights
ReplyDeleteThis brief notes are detailed Private Tutor Chandler
ReplyDeleteThe brief note is informative Private tutor Naples
ReplyDelete