Chapter Seventeen
Passage to the Nuremberg Rectorate, End of Fall 1808
Niethammer had been called to Munich and had a class there. [He had become
a Commissioner of Education in Bavaria in 1807.] He offered a post at a
Gymnasium in Nuremberg to Hegel, who was glad of it. It turned out Paulus was
also interested in the position when he heard of it. "Thus was Pegasus harnessed
to the plough of a school", says Rosenkranz. Yet, he goes on, it was not such a
bad thing. Although Hegel aimed at a university post, the German universities
under Napoleon had little freedom between 1808 and 1813; and Hegel had already
been a tutor for eight years and so had a practical grasp of teaching. All Hegel's letters from Nuremberg express satisfaction with his lot, though he
never lost sight of possibilities in the universities.
At the Aegidiengymnasium of Nuremberg, Hegel had to teach philosophy. In
doing so, he further increased the attention he had begun to pay at Jena to the
relations of non philosophical consciousness and speculation. [To interject, I
wonder if there is not an unnecessary dualism at work here, but I think this is
developed elsewhere. - SC]
Chapter Eighteen
Hegel as a Teacher
[Osmo first notes that Rosenkranz edited Volume 17 of the Werke of Hegel
that includes the Philosophical Propaedeutic. His experience at the
Aegidiengymnasium increased his clarity of expression, thinks Rosenkranz.]
Hegel was indefatigable as a teacher. Until 1812, he rewrote his courses
thoroughly each semester and adapted them to the age of the pupils. He taught
philosophy and religion, though in the absence of other teachers, he could turn
his hand to Greek and even mathematics (calculus). In his principal classes, he
dictated paragraphs, then explained them. He used tobacco. Pupils had to make
fair copies and were asked to summarise the last lesson orally in the next
class. They could ask questions in class. He addressed the pupils formally (as
Monsieur, presumably Herr) to encourage responsibility. The school overall was
a success.
From 1811 and more so after the retreat from Moscow reaction grew against
French oppression. As Rector, Hegel remained outwardly aloof and impartial.
However, Rosenkranz remarks that: "In town, and above all amongst the teaching staff, he passed for a
Francophile." (403) He did not encourage a German reading group amongst the pupils though,
recommending Homer instead. The group continued clandestinely. [To interject,
my impression from Rosenkranz is that Hegel was more a steady influence than an
agitator.] He insisted on religious observance by both Catholic and Protestant
pupils.
Hegel dressed in a grey suit and hat, properly but without ostentation. In
the evenings, he read the newspapers in the Nuremberg Musee (which had a reading
room). [Reading rooms had become a social institution in Europe at this time. -SC]
Socially, he visited Paulus (the editor of Spinoza) and Seebeck. He took an
interest in the researches of the latter into the theory of colours of Goethe.
He was an examiner of philosophy teachers, for which purpose he set questions on
the history of philosophy.
Five talks on teaching by Hegel, given on school prize days, are contained
in Werke 16 (there is also a French edition edited by B Bourgeois, but I do not
recall hearing of this in English yet.) In these, he sees the school as a
medium between the family and public life. Rosenkranz polemicises at this point
that there is a great deal of ethical content here, as there is in the
Philosophy of Right, arguing against those who deny an ethical content in
Hegel. Hegel argued that the study of the ancients gives a sense of wholeness
that modern life with its distinct trades and professions does not facilitate.
[This thought is more associated with Adam Smith in the UK, but seems to reflect
a concern of the era.] There is a similar talk on the retirement of Schenk, his
predecessor. The individual pupil, says Hegel, is animated by the life around
him: family, school, country, church. Rosenkranz refers to a faulty edition of
these talks in 1835 and to a newspaper critique where the faults were
identified.
Chapter Nineteen
The Philosophical Propaedeutic 1808 to 1812
Bavarian standards for philosophy teachers were contained in a directive,
which Rosenkranz reproduces. The teaching was intended to lead up to a
Speculative standpoint and to deal with ideas as its end at a university
entrance level. For students for whom this aimed too high, the content of the
course would start with logic (using Lambert and Plouquet as texts); followed by
cosmology and natural theology; then psychology, ethics and juridical concepts
(with Carus and Kant as texts); and finally what was called Philosophical
Encyclopaedia, a view of the whole. [This sounds ambitious enough to me, though
something of the sort is attempted in the last year of French secondary
education. - SC] Hegel changed this, proceeding instead:
- Lower class: law, morality and religion
- Middle class: psychology and logic (including the antinomies of Kant)
- Higher class: Encyclopaedia (per the directive)
This latter covered syllogism, scientific method, phenomenology, the State
and religion. He wrote a report to Niethammer on this initiative (see SW17), in
which he explains that the ethical subject matter was more adapted to the
students. Rosenkranz edited the Philosophical Propaedeutic himself (SW18) and
says that it was decisive for Hegel, who learned to combine brevity and
precision.
In the Propaedeutic, Hegel formulated the following tripartite plan for
Logic:
1. Objective Logic
- Being
- Essence (essence as such, proposition, ground)
- Reality (Wirklichkeit)
2. Subjective Logic
- Concept
- Judgement
- Syllogism (incorporating the idea of goal)
3. Doctrine of Ideas
- Life
- Knowing and Willing
- Science as System
These, Rosenkranz comments, mark and advance on the Jena structure. [To
comment, it also diverges from the published Science of Logic, and in fact makes
more sense to me than the published version. I have always had difficulty
seeing the subjective logic as a consequence of the objective logic on analogy
with the development of metaphysical ideas in the first part and indeed seeing
how the concluding path to the absolute idea was a part of subjective logic as
such. I suppose the third part corresponds loosely to the concept of definition
in Aristotle.]
Rosenkranz remarks finally that in the philosophy of mind there is greater
attention to subjective mental phenomena, namely intuition, imagination, memory,
language, etc.
Chapter Twenty
Hegel's Marriage, Autumn 1811
Hegel's life was characterised by tranquil progress and organic
maturity. There was no rush to action, but matters were brought to fruition in
due course. In this spirit, says Rosenkranz, Hegel married at age 40. In the
17th and 18th centuries, Descartes, Spinoza, Malebranche, Locke, Hume and Kant
had remained bachelors. Fichte was the first modern philosopher of world
importance to marry, as did Herbart and Schelling. Christiane, Hegel’s sister,
rejoiced for him.
His wife, Marie von Tucher (1791 to 1857) was from a noble family with
local roots. Her father had been a Burgermeister of Nuremberg. She reflected
the feelings Hegel had for her. They complemented each other as personalities,
which leads Rosenkranz to praise her vivacity and imagination. Rosenkranz
reproduces some verses that Hegel wrote for her. She seems like a joyful and
assured person to judge from the anecdotes relating to her and letters by her.
Some explanations were required during the engagement. She took offence or was
concerned by an expression he used: "in as much as happiness is my destiny in this world." Hegel thought marriage was essentially religious. He wrote a letter saying
that happiness is tinged with melancholy in higher natures and arguing that she
had promised to heal him from what led him away from belief in happiness. Love
is our love, not mine for you and yours for me, he says.
The couple married on 16 September 1811. A daughter died in early childhood (of
a suffocating catarrh). They had two sons: Karl Hegel (1813 to 1901) who became
a professor of history and Immanuel Hegel (1814 to 1891) who became a civil
servant. Karl Hegel edited the second edition of The Philosophy of History in
1848, the first having been edited by Edouard Gans in 1837. He also produced
the first edition of the Correspondence (1887), says Osmo.
Hegel was an attentive husband. His homes were functional more than
elegant. The family had a servant, but only one, save after children were
born. He kept household accounts. In Berlin, his flat was well situated. You
entered the sitting room straight from the corridor. He and Marie enjoyed
excursions as a way of relaxing. They visited Niethammer and his wife in Munich
who return visited.
Chapter 21
Hegel's Relations with the Philosophers of his Time
Rosenkranz notes that Hegel slowly emerged as a central figure in the
German philosophy of his time, taking up contemporary debates in his own work.
At this time, those around him included:
- followers of Schelling (such as Ast, Kanne and Goerres)
- more detached followers of Schelling (such as Steffens, Oken, Stutzmann,
Klein)
- those leaning towards Hegel.
Schelling's Philosophical Researches on the Essence of Human Freedom (1809) had sown the seeds of a intended reply to Hegel. Another thinker,
Wagner, tried to unify logic and mathematics. Herbart in Königsberg was an
isolated figure who anyway published his major works late in Hegel's life. In an important
piece of publicity, Bachmann reviewed the Phenomenology in the Heidelberger
Jahrbucher in 1810.
There is correspondence with Isaak von Sinclair (1775-1815), Karl Windischmann (1775-1839), Nicolaus von Thalen (d1848), Berger of Kiel, Karl Solger (1780-1819) and van Ghert. Of these Sinclair and Solger are the most important. It is typical of Rosenkranz that he summarises the relations between Hegel and his contemporaries, leaving room for further investigations into who they were and what the significance of their relationship with Hegel was. Since Rosenkranz wrote, much of this correspondence has been published. In general, more evidence of interest in Spinoza emerges here.
Isaak von Sinclair
Hegel kept up relations with Isaak von Sinclair (1775-1815). This I
think is often overlooked in English commentaries as Sinclair is not known in
English language philosophical literature. However, the letters between them are
interesting. Hegel reserved holidays for replying to letters and often only a
sketch of his reply survives rather than the actual letter. Sinclair had
written poetry and tragedy, but had recently published three volumes of
philosophy under the title Truth and Certainty (1811) This gave rise to an exchange of letters. Hegel writes asking if Sinclair
is still relentlessly Fichtean and what does he say about the progress to
infinity. He writes to Sinclair:
"I am an educator who has to teach philosophy, and that is perhaps why it is my conviction that philosophy must be a structured edifice, as well as geometry, which can be taught as well as it." (429)
The content of philosophy is one thing, creative talent another, he
continues, saying that he wishes to add to the scientific form. He recalls how
from doleful Frankfurt he looked at Feldberg and Altkoenig, mountains of the
Taurus range.
The work of Sinclair begins of doubt, which is a medium between certainty
and ignorance. This sounds similar to ideas that Hegel had already absorbed from
Sextus Empiricus. In his book, Sinclair passes in review relations to self,
world and God from something of a Fichtean standpoint. Doubt again is a midpoint
between life and science. Hegel writes to Sinclair:
"It is above all the new philosophers who demand a beginning that would be an absolute to which they would not straight away oppose their verbiage, an irrefutable first..." (431)
The non-philosopher wants to bring in his own understanding, full of common
sense. There is a note of irritation here, I think. He and Sinclair had been
sufficiently methodical in starting out, he thinks, in their different ways. A
beginning is bound to be imperfect, just because it is a beginning. Yet, he
continues, it must be a beginning of philosophy, and therefore already
philosophy itself. Sinclair on the other hand starts with a need for philosophy
and Hegel disagrees with this. Hegel writes:
"I assuredly agree with you that one cannot start blindly. The point is that the beginning be essentially a beginning of philosophy. In consequence, I require for the beginning still more than you do, that it already itself be, in fact and in substance, philosophy and avow itself as such, that it thus be more than the need alone of philosophy, but also not more than it can be as a beginning of philosophy." (432)
An analysis of doubt such as Sinclair includes, itself brings in a lot of
philosophy indirectly, in an underhand way. Sinclair smuggles in contraband
goods. He admits doubt as a fact. Hegel says that his own beginning is a fact,
the immediate. This is a beginning because it is not yet progress. He
writes:
"Now contraband is forbidden by Imperial decree and it would be necessary that a tribunal should recognise already, in the unwarranted character of this activity a metaphysics or an ideology." (431)
This is a rare reference to Idéologie by Hegel, writes Osmo, for the terms
are in French in the text. The content of doubt is already more than immediacy.
He writes “My sole and unique goal is to teach in a university.” (433) The
tumult of the present day leaves little room for expenditure on universities,
still less for metaphysics. Ministerial priorities are the professions – law,
medicine, theology – but of these philosophy is a foundation (see Correspondance
II, letter 218) Sinclair soon died at the Congress of Vienna and is now (1844)
forgotten.
Karl Windischmann
Hegel discussed Catholicism and medicine with Windischmann. In 1810,
Windischmann wrote that the Phenomenology was a manual of human liberation, like
the key to the gospel that Lessing had announced. He tried to relate religion in
medicine, to awaken the priest in the doctor, as he put it. He was also
interested in somnambulism and annotated a translation of De Maistre's Soirées
de Saint Petersbourg (1824). This of course was a famous text of the Restoration
similar to Reflections on the Revolution in France of Burke. He praised the
review of Aphorisms on absolute Knowing and not Knowing by Göschel (see
Rosenkranz III,15). Hegel later thought he saw plagiarism in Windischmann's
Philosophy in the Course of World History (4 vols, 1824 to 34).
Nicolaus von Thalen
He discussed Protestantism and political economy with von Thalen. Thalen
was a Danish student at Flensburg who knew Reinhold and had studied philosophy
at Kiel. He also knew Hulsen of the League of Free Men and Rosenkranz says more
of him in his edition of volume 23 of Kant s Werke. He sought rational precision
rather than the mystical enthusiasm of Windischmann. He responded to the Logic
and wrote on it in 1815. The Science of Logic had been given three reviews, by
Fries, Krug and an anonymous reviewer, published in Heidelberg, Halle and
Leipzig. By 1816, Hegel had accepted a post at Heidelberg in preference to
Erlangen and suggestions from Berlin which came later. He says that up to then
he had worked in quasi solitude. A university post is necessary to disseminate a
philosophy and personal contact will improve his ability to express it.
Thalen liked the First Edition of the Encyclopaedia and the essay on the
Wurttemberg Estates, but not so much the Philosophy of Right (1821) and in
particular its defence of primogeniture (paras 305 to 307). Pride is a fault of
philosophers, he reminds Hegel, whom he accuses (wrongly) of having written
about Fries and Schopenhauer in the Wiener Jahrbucher. He offered various
advice, e.g. about calming the dispute with Schleiermacher.
Berger
Berger of Kiel published an Elements of Science that drew syncretically on
Kant and Schelling. He had a typically North German sense of pious attention to
the secular and its duties. Like Sinclair, he is now forgotten, Rosenkranz
remarks.
Karl Solger
Karl Solger was a medium between Hegel and Schelling, but only knew Hegel
when he went to Berlin. In fact, Solger proposed Hegel to Berlin, but dies a
year later. Solger studied Spinoza. Rosenkranz has much of interest to say about him, but it is the Berlin part of the book in connection with Hegel's review of his posthumous writings.
Van Ghert
Hegel had a Dutch pupil, van Ghert, who was later helpful to him. Van
Ghert stayed in Amsterdam and later Brussels where he had administrative posts.
He offered to help Hegel, commenting that the Dutch liked Spinoza, but not
Kantian philosophy in general. Hegel asked if he knew of any manuscripts of
Spinoza and van Ghert identified a Hebrew grammar. He sent Hegel an edition of
Jacob Boehme. His interests included animal magnetism (see
SW16, 475 to 483).
Please advise on how to locate Five talks on teaching by Hegel, given on school prize days, while in Nuremberg between 1808-1816. Thanks.
ReplyDeleteThere is an English translation of one speech in Miscellaneous Writings of GWF Hegel. Ed. Jon Stewart. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 2002 and a selection in Millicent Mackenzie. Hegel's Educational Theory and Practice. London, 1909. There's a cheap German version in Nürnberger und Heidelberger Schriften. Werke 4. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970. The French version is GWF Hegel: Textes pédagogiques. Ed. B Bourgeois. Paris Vrin, 1990. Hegel also describes the transition to adult life very movingly in the Philosophy of Spirit.
ReplyDeleteThank you. I noticed that it is mentioned in the post that they are contained in Werke 16. I found a 2010 book on Amazon, "Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Werke, Volume 16 by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Karl Rosenkranz and Heinrich Gustav Hotho", and it is specified as in English. Are you aware of this book? Thanks again.
DeleteSuperb, there's a PDF copy available here - https://archive.org/details/b1641148
Delete"Werke" says German to me.
ReplyDelete