This post reproduces Stephen Cowley's article in the John Macmurray Fellowship Newsletter 24 (2009). The article relates some central ideas of the personalist philosopher John Macmurray (1891-1976) to those of his British Idealist teachers in Glasgow (see photo above, from Kelvingrove Park) and Oxford. The Idealist movement flourished in Victorian and early 20th century Britain, seeking to develop ideas drawn from Kant and Hegel by way of a critique of contemporary empiricist and scientific thought on society and the nature of the mind.
The John Macmurray Fellowship website can be found here.
The John Macmurray Fellowship website can be found here.
John Macmurray's early Milieu
John Macmurray’s writings call us to identify and reflect on the
primacy of personal relations within experience. However, the originality of the philosophical
position from which he developed his ideas on the nature of persons has been
overstated and the way in which these arose from earlier philosophical concepts
has remained opaque to several commentators on his thought. ARC Duncan for example, states that Macmurray
“adhere[d] to no particular school”, [1]
whilst others are inclined to attribute his thought to a peculiar sensitivity
to personal relations. This he may
indeed have possessed, but it is not a sufficient explanation of his
philosophy.
Macmurray deliberately set aside his learning to put his thoughts
across in plain words to a popular audience. [2]
The resultant lack of citations has served to make tracking down his
philosophical antecedents a tricky business, as has the sale of his personal
library and destruction of records noted by John Costello. [3] This
is worth doing though, as a lack of understanding of how Macmurray approached
philosophy prevents new work being done in the same vein, the reverse of what
Macmurray himself wanted.
I wish to argue then, that many of Macmurray’s ideas can be found in
germ in the writings of the leading Glasgow Idealist Edward Caird
(1835-1908). This on its own would not
prove “influence”, for the possibilities of a common source or even
co-incidental joint discovery would remain.
However, knowledge of Macmurray’s early milieu makes this
improbable.
Caird’s influence, coupled historically with that of Thomas Hill Green
(1836-82) as the liberal wing of the Idealist movement, was vast. Robert Wenley cites the Spectator on
the high regard in which Caird was held: “His examination of the Kantian
philosophy is one of the two or three original philosophical works that Great
Britain has given to the world during the latter half of this century.” [4]
The reference here is to The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1889,
2nd edition 1909). His pupil
and Macmurray’s tutor, AD Lindsay (1879-1952), echoed this in describing his
teaching: “You knew that what he said must be ultimately right, however much
the details might work out differently.” [5]
Amongst many other sources that might be quoted to the same effect, I will add
only Macmurray’s own passing reference to “Caird’s great work on the ‘Critical
Philosophy of Kant’”, [6] one of two works
named by him in his 1926 review of modern British philosophy, the other being
Bernard Bosanquet’s The Philosophical Theory of the State (1899), itself
an application of Idealist concepts to political theory.
Macmurray studied philosophy firstly at Glasgow University, where he
attended the class of Robert Latta (1865-1932) and most likely knew Henry Jones
(1852-1922), [7] the
Welsh protégé of Caird. Latta’s book on
Leibniz [8]
contains a version of Caird’s ideas.
Jones described his students: “They knew the technical terms in common
use, and had begun to find their way about in philosophical literature. And above all, they had learned, or at least
had been taught, to work for themselves, without looking to professorial
prelections for every point of the law.” [9]
As Macmurray won the class prize in Latta’s class in his second of four
years study, we may suppose this description applies a fortiori to him
and thus that Costello underestimates Glasgow’s formative influence on
Macmurray. In 1913 he went on to Balliol College,
Oxford, where he studied philosophy more deeply under AD Lindsay and alongside
another idealist philosopher Charles Morris.
In the light of this, it is reasonable to look closely at the work of
Caird cited by Macmurray for shared ideas.
I find three such central ideas there: the “unity of experience”; the
critical relation of philosophy and common sense; and a version of the “form of
the personal” under the name “form of self-consciousness”. I will expound Caird’s account of these to
illustrate the similarities with Macmurray’s ideas.
The unity of experience
The first and most important of these common ideas is that of the
unity of experience, for it quite fundamental to Macmurray’s approach to a
range of subjects and the root of his opposition to “dualism”. The basic idea is that distinctions within
experience (mind and matter, state and society, work and leisure, for example)
presuppose and can only arise within a prior sense of unity. Caird writes: “The unity of all experience,
of all objects with each other and with the mind that knows them, is, so to
speak, the horizon within which all special objects are determined”. [10]
This unity is thus present in the “ordinary experience” he seeks to
understand and which equates to Macmurray’s “immediate experience” [11]
as a starting point of reflection.
Caird summarises the implications of this for philosophical method:
“Hence the object of the critical philosopher must be, not to dismiss any of
the elements of experience that he may find the pure expression of truth in
what remains, but rather to correct an abstract and incomplete view of the
world by taking account of the factors which that view neglects.” [12]
This is Macmurray’s project too, expressed in the criteria of adequacy
and coherence by which he evaluates constructive philosophy.
On philosophy and common sense
One
aspect of this is the unity of knowledge, which is a reflection of experience
other than when it limits itself by some particular purpose. Caird summarised this to his students: “I
have a number of principles in the mind which seem to carry with them
necessity, - geometrical axioms, causality, substance and quality, etc.” These examples are plainly derived from Kant,
though they might as well be illustrated by any common sense axiom. Caird continues though, that “to suppose that
the mind has such ideas in it, primary and unconnected, would almost destroy
the mind’s unity.” [13]
In
this respect, Caird opposed the Scottish common sense philosophy to which
Macmurray’s thought is sometimes misleadingly assimilated. For example, he wrote that philosophy must
“distinguish itself from the ordinary opinion or common sense of men by two
marks: it must raise into clear consciousness what is latent in common sense,
the laws and the principles that underlie our common experience and knowledge;
and secondly, it must bring its thoughts together, and discover their mutual
relation, instead of passing from the one to the other and forgetting each in
turn.” [14]
It is in the second of these marks that the contrast with common sense
advocates such as Thomas Reid, GE Moore and JL Austin emerges.
The form of self-consciousness
Within
experience as a whole, both Caird and Macmurray discern three forms. The first two, the mechanical and organic
they hold in common, whilst the “form of self-consciousness” found in Caird
foreshadows Macmurray’s “form of the personal”. In his attempt to develop the
form of self-consciousness, Caird approaches in places the formulation of
Macmurray in terms of a positive that supersedes its negative limits. He says for example: “Asceticism, or a movement in which the
ascetic idea is involved, may fairly be said to be the beginning of
morality. When, however, this negation
is conceived absolutely, the positive reconstitution of the natural life in any
form becomes impossible.” [15]
And again: “A negative which does not spring from a positive, and does not
contain the germ of a new positive, is an impossible abstraction.” [16]
This critique of Kant and Stoicism he develops based on a concept of the
“self as active” which transforms, rather than merely observing or negating,
its desires. Readers of Macmurray’s The
Self as Agent (1957) will observe the similarity.
Conclusion
In conclusion, those seeking to develop Macmurray’s ideas would be
well advised to relate them to their background in the Idealist movement. These are not the only influences or contexts
that make sense of his ideas, [17]
but they are certainly amongst those of fundamental significance. In addition to the points argued above, such
features of Macmurray’s thought as the critiques of Descartes and Kant were
staple fare in Glasgow. In this respect,
behind the immediate personal influence of Latta, Jones and AD Lindsay lies the
work of Edward Caird, whose ideas were put in more popular form in his lectures
on The Evolution of Religion (1893).
A knowledge of Caird’s work adds strength in depth to our understanding
of John Macmurray’s philosophical project.
[1]
ARC Duncan: On the Nature of Persons (NY: Lang, 1990), p2.
[2] He
describes this in the published radio talks Freedom in the Modern World.
(London: Faber, 1932), pp16-17.
[3]
John Costello: John Macmurray: A Biography, (Edinburgh: Floris, 2002),
p99.
[4] Robert
Wenley: ‘Some Lights on the British Idealist Movement in the Nineteenth
Century’, in The American Journal of Theology (1901), pp445-6.
[5] AD
Lindsay Letter to Muirhead, 31 Sept 1920, Glasgow UL MS Gen 1475/22.
[6] John Macmurray: ‘The
Influence of British Philosophy During “Those Forty Years”’, in The British
Weekly 81:2089, (11 Nov, 1926), pp164-5.
[7] He notes
Jones’ influence in Scotland in the 1926 article, refers familiarly to “Harry
Jones” and uses Jones’ phrase “as a practical creed” in correspondence (from
Jones’ Idealism as a Practical Creed).
[8] Leibniz:
the Monadology and Other Philosophical Writings (Oxford: Clarendon, 1898),
particularly Latta’s long introductory essay.
[9]
HJW Hetherington, Life and Letters of Sir Henry Jones (1924), p72.
[10]
Caird, Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant (Glasgow: Maclehose, 1889),
vol I, pp294-5.
[11] For
example, Macmurray’s Interpreting the Universe (London: Faber, 1933),
p7.
[12]
Caird, 1889, vol II, p641.
[13] GUL: MS Gen 104/1.
p16.
[14] Caird, The
Philosophy of Kant (Glasgow: MacLehose, 1877), p34.
[15]
Caird, 1889, vol II p203.
[16]
Caird, 1889, vol II p214.
[17] Most
notably, the influence of the French phenomenological tradition and the
psychologies of William James and GF Stout are outside the scope of this
article. Macmurray’s exposure to both
seems to have begun at Glasgow.
Thanks for this. There were some interesting and generally favourable comments in later issues of the JMF Newsletter too.
ReplyDeleteThis report is arranged fantastically, the author appear to be expert and serious enough to justify the historical facts related to the subject. overall, this is a educational resources kaise online blog
ReplyDelete